work assignments

 

Mathematics

From Wikipedia, the free encyclopediaThis article is about the field of study. For other uses, see and .Greek mathematician (holding ), 3rd century BC, as imagined by in this detail from (15091511)Nuvola Math and Inf.svgMathematics

Navigation

Mathematics (from : , mthma, ‘knowledge, study, learning’) includes the study of such topics as (), (), (), and (). It has no generally accepted .

Mathematicians seek and use to formulate new ; they resolve the or falsity of such by . When are good models of real phenomena, mathematical reasoning can be used to provide insight or predictions about nature. Through the use of and , mathematics developed from , , , and the systematic study of the and of . Practical mathematics has been a human activity from as far back as exist. The required to solve mathematical problems can take years or even centuries of sustained inquiry.

first appeared in , most notably in ‘s . Since the pioneering work of (18581932), (18621943), and others , it has become customary to view mathematical research as establishing truth by from appropriately chosen and . Mathematics developed at a relatively slow pace until the , when mathematical innovations interacting with new led to a rapid increase in the rate of mathematical discovery that has continued to the present day.

Mathematics is essential in many fields, including , , , , and the . has led to entirely new mathematical disciplines, such as and . Mathematicians engage in (mathematics for its own sake) without having any application in mind, but practical applications for what began as pure mathematics are often discovered later.

Contents

History

Main article:

The history of mathematics can be seen as an ever-increasing series of . The first abstraction, which is shared by many animals, was probably that of numbers: the realization that a collection of two apples and a collection of two oranges (for example) have something in common, namely the quantity of their members.

As evidenced by found on bone, in addition to recognizing how to physical objects, peoples may have also recognized how to count abstract quantities, like timedays, seasons, or years.

The Babylonian mathematical tablet Plimpton 322, dated to 1800 BC.

Evidence for more complex mathematics does not appear until around 3000 , when the and Egyptians began using , and for taxation and other financial calculations, for building and construction, and for . The oldest mathematical texts from and are from 2000 to 1800 BC. Many early texts mention and so, by inference, the seems to be the most ancient and widespread mathematical development after basic arithmetic and geometry. It is in that (, , and ) first appear in the archaeological record. The Babylonians also possessed a place-value system and used a numeral system which is still in use today for measuring angles and time.

Archimedes used the to approximate the value of .

Beginning in the 6th century BC with the , with the began a systematic study of mathematics as a subject in its own right. Around 300 BC, introduced the still used in mathematics today, consisting of definition, axiom, theorem, and proof. His book, , is widely considered the most successful and influential textbook of all time. The greatest mathematician of antiquity is often held to be (c. 287212 BC) of . He developed formulas for calculating the surface area and volume of and used the to calculate the under the arc of a with the , in a manner not too dissimilar from modern calculus. Other notable achievements of Greek mathematics are (, 3rd century BC), (, 2nd century BC), and the beginnings of algebra (, 3rd century AD).

The numerals used in the , dated between the 2nd century BC and the 2nd century AD.

The and the rules for the use of its operations, in use throughout the world today, evolved over the course of the first millennium AD in and were transmitted to the via . Other notable developments of Indian mathematics include the modern definition and approximation of and , and an early form of .

A page from al-Khwrizm’s Algebra

During the , especially during the 9th and 10th centuries, mathematics saw many important innovations building on Greek mathematics. The most notable achievement of was the development of . Other achievements of the Islamic period include advances in and the addition of the to the Arabic numeral system. Many notable mathematicians from this period were Persian, such as , and .

During the , mathematics began to develop at an accelerating pace in . The development of by Newton and Leibniz in the 17th century revolutionized mathematics. was the most notable mathematician of the 18th century, contributing numerous theorems and discoveries. Perhaps the foremost mathematician of the 19th century was the German mathematician , who made numerous contributions to fields such as , , , , , and . In the early 20th century, transformed mathematics by publishing his , which show in part that any consistent axiomatic systemif powerful enough to describe arithmeticwill contain true propositions that cannot be proved.

Mathematics has since been greatly extended, and there has been a fruitful interaction between mathematics and , to the benefit of both. Mathematical discoveries continue to be made today. According to Mikhail B. Sevryuk, in the January 2006 issue of the , “The number of papers and books included in the database since 1940 (the first year of operation of MR) is now more than 1.9 million, and more than 75 thousand items are added to the database each year. The overwhelming majority of works in this ocean contain new mathematical and their .”

Etymology

The word mathematics comes from mthma (), meaning “that which is learnt,” “what one gets to know,” hence also “study” and “science”. The word for “mathematics” came to have the narrower and more technical meaning “mathematical study” even in Classical times. Its is mathmatiks (), meaning “related to learning” or “studious,” which likewise further came to mean “mathematical.” In particular, mathmatik tkhn ( ; : ars mathematica) meant “the mathematical art.”

Similarly, one of the two main schools of thought in was known as the mathmatikoi ()which at the time meant “learners” rather than “mathematicians” in the modern sense.

In Latin, and in English until around 1700, the term mathematics more commonly meant “” (or sometimes “”) rather than “mathematics”; the meaning gradually changed to its present one from about 1500 to 1800. This has resulted in several mistranslations. For example, ‘s warning that Christians should beware of mathematici, meaning astrologers, is sometimes mistranslated as a condemnation of mathematicians.

The apparent form in English, like the French plural form les mathmatiques (and the less commonly used singular la mathmatique), goes back to the Latin plural mathematica (), based on the Greek plural ta mathmatik ( ), used by (384322 BC), and meaning roughly “all things mathematical”, although it is plausible that English borrowed only the adjective mathematic(al) and formed the noun mathematics anew, after the pattern of and , which were inherited from Greek. In English, the noun mathematics takes a singular verb. It is often shortened to maths or, in North America, math.

Definitions of mathematics

, the Italian mathematician who introduced the invented between the 1st and 4th centuries by Indian mathematicians, to the Western World.Main article:

Mathematics has no generally accepted definition. defined mathematics as “the science of quantity” and this definition prevailed until the 18th century. However, Aristotle also noted a focus on quantity alone may not distinguish mathematics from sciences like physics; in his view, abstraction and studying quantity as a property “separable in thought” from real instances set mathematics apart.

In the 19th century, when the study of mathematics increased in rigor and began to address abstract topics such as and , which have no clear-cut relation to quantity and measurement, mathematicians and philosophers began to propose a variety of new definitions.

A great many professional mathematicians take no interest in a definition of mathematics, or consider it undefinable. There is not even consensus on whether mathematics is an art or a science. Some just say, “Mathematics is what mathematicians do.”

Three leading types

Three leading types of definition of mathematics today are called , , and , each reflecting a different philosophical school of thought. All have severe flaws, none has widespread acceptance, and no reconciliation seems possible.

Logicist definitions

An early definition of mathematics in terms of logic was that of (1870): “the science that draws necessary conclusions.” In the , and advanced the philosophical program known as , and attempted to prove that all mathematical concepts, statements, and principles can be defined and proved entirely in terms of . A logicist definition of mathematics is Russell’s (1903) “All Mathematics is Symbolic Logic.”

Intuitionist definitions

definitions, developing from the philosophy of mathematician , identify mathematics with certain mental phenomena. An example of an intuitionist definition is “Mathematics is the mental activity which consists in carrying out constructs one after the other.” A peculiarity of intuitionism is that it rejects some mathematical ideas considered valid according to other definitions. In particular, while other philosophies of mathematics allow objects that can be proved to exist even though they cannot be constructed, intuitionism allows only mathematical objects that one can actually construct. Intuitionists also reject the (i.e., {displaystyle Pvee neg P}{displaystyle Pvee neg P}). While this stance does force them to reject one common version of as a viable proof method, namely the inference of {displaystyle P}P from {displaystyle neg Pto bot }{displaystyle neg Pto bot }, they are still able to infer {displaystyle neg P}neg P from {displaystyle Pto bot }Pto bot. For them, {displaystyle neg (neg P)}{displaystyle neg (neg P)} is a strictly weaker statement than {displaystyle P}P.

Formalist definitions

definitions identify mathematics with its symbols and the rules for operating on them. defined mathematics simply as “the science of formal systems”. A is a set of symbols, or tokens, and some rules on how the tokens are to be combined into formulas. In formal systems, the word axiom has a special meaning different from the ordinary meaning of “a self-evident truth”, and is used to refer to a combination of tokens that is included in a given formal system without needing to be derived using the rules of the system.

Mathematics as science

, known as the prince of mathematicians

The German mathematician referred to mathematics as “the Queen of the Sciences”. More recently, has called mathematics “the Queen of Science … the main driving force behind scientific discovery”. The philosopher observed that “most mathematical theories are, like those of and , -: pure mathematics therefore turns out to be much closer to the natural sciences whose hypotheses are conjectures, than it seemed even recently.” Popper also noted that “I shall certainly admit a system as empirical or scientific only if it is capable of being tested by experience.”

Several authors consider that mathematics is not a science because it does not rely on .

Mathematics shares much in common with many fields in the physical sciences, notably the of assumptions. and experimentation also play a role in the formulation of in both mathematics and the (other) sciences. continues to grow in importance within mathematics, and computation and simulation are playing an increasing role in both the sciences and mathematics.

The opinions of mathematicians on this matter are varied. Many mathematicians feel that to call their area a science is to downplay the importance of its aesthetic side, and its history in the traditional seven ; others feel that to ignore its connection to the sciences is to turn a blind eye to the fact that the interface between mathematics and its applications in science and engineering has driven much development in mathematics. One way this difference of viewpoint plays out is in the philosophical debate as to whether mathematics is created (as in art) or discovered (as in science). In practice, mathematicians are typically grouped with scientists at the gross level but separated at finer levels. This is one of many issues considered in the .

Inspiration, pure and applied mathematics, and aesthetics

Main article: Isaac NewtonGottfried Wilhelm von Leibniz (left) and developed infinitesimal calculus.

Mathematics arises from many different kinds of problems. At first these were found in commerce, , architecture and later ; today, all sciences suggest problems studied by mathematicians, and many problems arise within mathematics itself. For example, the invented the of using a combination of mathematical reasoning and physical insight, and today’s , a still-developing scientific theory which attempts to unify the four , continues to inspire new mathematics.

Some mathematics is relevant only in the area that inspired it, and is applied to solve further problems in that area. But often mathematics inspired by one area proves useful in many areas, and joins the general stock of mathematical concepts. A distinction is often made between and . However pure mathematics topics often turn out to have applications, e.g. in .

This remarkable fact, that even the “purest” mathematics often turns out to have practical applications, is what the physicist has named “”. The has written extensively on this matter and acknowledges that the applicability of mathematics constitutes a challenge to naturalism. For the philosopher of mathematics , the fact that the physical world acts in accordance with the dictates of non-causal mathematical entities existing beyond the universe is “a happy coincidence”. On the other hand, for some , connections, which are acquired among mathematical things, just mirror the connections acquiring among objects in the universe, so that there is no “happy coincidence”.

As in most areas of study, the explosion of knowledge in the scientific age has led to specialization: there are now hundreds of specialized areas in mathematics and the latest runs to 46 pages. Several areas of applied mathematics have merged with related traditions outside of mathematics and become disciplines in their own right, including statistics, , and .

For those who are mathematically inclined, there is often a definite aesthetic aspect to much of mathematics. Many mathematicians talk about the elegance of mathematics, its intrinsic and inner beauty. and generality are valued. There is beauty in a simple and elegant , such as ‘s proof that there are infinitely many , and in an elegant that speeds calculation, such as the . in expressed the belief that these aesthetic considerations are, in themselves, sufficient to justify the study of pure mathematics. He identified criteria such as significance, unexpectedness, inevitability, and economy as factors that contribute to a mathematical aesthetic. Mathematical research often seeks critical features of a mathematical object. A theorem expressed as a of the object by these features is the prize. Examples of particularly succinct and revelatory mathematical arguments have been published in .

The popularity of is another sign of the pleasure many find in solving mathematical questions. And at the other social extreme, philosophers continue to find problems in , such as the nature of .

Notation, language, and rigor

Main article: created and popularized much of the mathematical notation used today.

Most of the mathematical notation in use today was not invented until the 16th century. Before that, mathematics was written out in words, limiting mathematical discovery. (17071783) was responsible for many of the notations in use today. Modern notation makes mathematics much easier for the professional, but beginners often find it daunting. According to , this can be attributed to the fact that mathematical ideas are both more abstract and more encrypted than those of natural language. Unlike natural language, where people can often equate a word (such as cow) with the physical object it corresponds to, mathematical symbols are abstract, lacking any physical analog. Mathematical symbols are also more highly encrypted than regular words, meaning a single symbol can encode a number of different operations or ideas.

can be difficult to understand for beginners because even common terms, such as or and only, have a more precise meaning than they have in everyday speech, and other terms such as and refer to specific mathematical ideas, not covered by their laymen’s meanings. Mathematical language also includes many technical terms such as and that have no meaning outside of mathematics. Additionally, shorthand phrases such as iff for “” belong to . There is a reason for special notation and technical vocabulary: mathematics requires more precision than everyday speech. Mathematicians refer to this precision of language and logic as “rigor”.

is fundamentally a matter of . Mathematicians want their theorems to follow from axioms by means of systematic reasoning. This is to avoid mistaken “”, based on fallible intuitions, of which many instances have occurred in the history of the subject. The level of rigor expected in mathematics has varied over time: the Greeks expected detailed arguments, but at the time of the methods employed were less rigorous. Problems inherent in the definitions used by Newton would lead to a resurgence of careful analysis and formal proof in the 19th century. Misunderstanding the rigor is a cause for some of the common misconceptions of mathematics. Today, mathematicians continue to argue among themselves about . Since large computations are hard to verify, such proofs may be erroneous if the used computer program is erroneous. On the other hand, allow verifying all details that cannot be given in a hand-written proof, and provide certainty of the correctness of long proofs such as that of the .

in traditional thought were “self-evident truths”, but that conception is problematic. At a formal level, an axiom is just a string of symbols, which has an intrinsic meaning only in the context of all derivable formulas of an . It was the goal of to put all of mathematics on a firm axiomatic basis, but according to every (sufficiently powerful) axiomatic system has formulas; and so a final of mathematics is impossible. Nonetheless mathematics is often imagined to be (as far as its formal content) nothing but in some axiomatization, in the sense that every mathematical statement or proof could be cast into formulas within set theory.

Fields of mathematics

See also: and The is a simple calculating tool used since ancient times.

Mathematics can, broadly speaking, be subdivided into the study of quantity, structure, space, and change (i.e. , , , and ). In addition to these main concerns, there are also subdivisions dedicated to exploring links from the heart of mathematics to other fields: to , to (), to the empirical mathematics of the various sciences (), and more recently to the rigorous study of . While some areas might seem unrelated, the has found connections between areas previously thought unconnected, such as , and .

conventionally groups together the fields of mathematics which study mathematical structures that are fundamentally discrete rather than continuous.

Foundations and philosophy

In order to clarify the , the fields of and were developed. Mathematical logic includes the mathematical study of and the applications of formal logic to other areas of mathematics; set theory is the branch of mathematics that studies or collections of objects. The phrase “crisis of foundations” describes the search for a rigorous foundation for mathematics that took place from approximately 1900 to 1930. Some disagreement about the foundations of mathematics continues to the present day. The crisis of foundations was stimulated by a number of controversies at the time, including the and the .

Mathematical logic is concerned with setting mathematics within a rigorous framework, and studying the implications of such a framework. As such, it is home to which (informally) imply that any effective that contains basic arithmetic, if sound (meaning that all theorems that can be proved are true), is necessarily incomplete (meaning that there are true theorems which cannot be proved in that system). Whatever finite collection of number-theoretical axioms is taken as a foundation, Gdel showed how to construct a formal statement that is a true number-theoretical fact, but which does not follow from those axioms. Therefore, no formal system is a complete axiomatization of full number theory. Modern logic is divided into , , and , and is closely linked to , as well as to . In the context of recursion theory, the impossibility of a full axiomatization of number theory can also be formally demonstrated as a .

includes , , and . Computability theory examines the limitations of various theoretical models of the computer, including the most well-known modelthe . Complexity theory is the study of tractability by computer; some problems, although theoretically solvable by computer, are so expensive in terms of time or space that solving them is likely to remain practically unfeasible, even with the rapid advancement of computer hardware. A famous problem is the “” problem, one of the . Finally, information theory is concerned with the amount of data that can be stored on a given medium, and hence deals with concepts such as and .

{displaystyle pRightarrow q}{displaystyle pRightarrow q}Venn A intersect B.svgCommutative diagram for morphism.svgDFAexample.svg

Pure mathematics

Main article:

Number systems and number theory

Main articles: , , and

The study of quantity starts with numbers, first the familiar {displaystyle mathbb {N} }mathbb {N} and {displaystyle mathbb {Z} }mathbb {Z} (“whole numbers”) and arithmetical operations on them, which are characterized in . The deeper properties of integers are studied in , from which come such popular results as . The conjecture and are two unsolved problems in number theory.

As the number system is further developed, the integers are recognized as a of the {displaystyle mathbb {Q} }mathbb {Q} (“”). These, in turn, are contained within the , {displaystyle mathbb {R} }mathbb {R} which are used to represent limits of sequences of rational numbers and quantities. Real numbers are generalized to the {displaystyle mathbb {C} }mathbb {C}. According to the , all polynomial in one unknown with complex coefficients have a solution in the complex numbers, regardless of degree of the polynomial. {displaystyle mathbb {N} , mathbb {Z} , mathbb {Q} , mathbb {R} }{displaystyle mathbb {N} , mathbb {Z} , mathbb {Q} , mathbb {R} } and {displaystyle mathbb {C} }mathbb {C} are the first steps of a hierarchy of numbers that goes on to include and . Consideration of the natural numbers also leads to the , which formalize the concept of “”. Another area of study is the size of sets, which is described with the . These include the , which allow meaningful comparison of the size of infinitely large sets.

{displaystyle (0),1,2,3,ldots }{displaystyle (0),1,2,3,ldots }{displaystyle ldots ,-2,-1,0,1,2,ldots }{displaystyle ldots ,-2,-1,0,1,2,ldots }{displaystyle -2,{frac {2}{3}},1.21}{displaystyle -2,{frac {2}{3}},1.21}{displaystyle -e,{sqrt {2}},3,pi }{displaystyle -e,{sqrt {2}},3,pi }{displaystyle 2,i,-2+3i,2e^{i{frac {4pi }{3}}}}{displaystyle 2,i,-2+3i,2e^{i{frac {4pi }{3}}}}{displaystyle aleph _{0},aleph _{1},aleph _{2},ldots ,aleph _{alpha },ldots . }{displaystyle aleph _{0},aleph _{1},aleph _{2},ldots ,aleph _{alpha },ldots . }

Structure

Main article:

Many mathematical objects, such as of numbers and , exhibit internal structure as a consequence of or that are defined on the set. Mathematics then studies properties of those sets that can be expressed in terms of that structure; for instance studies properties of the set of that can be expressed in terms of operations. Moreover, it frequently happens that different such structured sets (or ) exhibit similar properties, which makes it possible, by a further step of , to state for a class of structures, and then study at once the whole class of structures satisfying these axioms. Thus one can study , , and other abstract systems; together such studies (for structures defined by algebraic operations) constitute the domain of .

By its great generality, abstract algebra can often be applied to seemingly unrelated problems; for instance a number of ancient problems concerning were finally solved using , which involves field theory and group theory. Another example of an algebraic theory is , which is the general study of , whose elements called have both quantity and direction, and can be used to model (relations between) points in space. This is one example of the phenomenon that the originally unrelated areas of and have very strong interactions in modern mathematics. studies ways of enumerating the number of objects that fit a given structure.

{displaystyle {begin{matrix}(1,2,3)&(1,3,2)\(2,1,3)&(2,3,1)\(3,1,2)&(3,2,1)end{matrix}}}{begin{matrix}(1,2,3)&(1,3,2)\(2,1,3)&(2,3,1)\(3,1,2)&(3,2,1)end{matrix}}Elliptic curve simple.svgRubik's cube.svgGroup diagdram D6.svgLattice of the divisibility of 60.svgBraid-modular-group-cover.svg

Space

Main article:

The study of space originates with in particular, , which combines space and numbers, and encompasses the well-known . is the branch of mathematics that deals with relationships between the sides and the angles of triangles and with the trigonometric functions. The modern study of space generalizes these ideas to include higher-dimensional geometry, (which play a central role in ) and . Quantity and space both play a role in , , and . and were developed to solve problems in and but now are pursued with an eye on applications in and . Within differential geometry are the concepts of and calculus on , in particular, and . Within algebraic geometry is the description of geometric objects as solution sets of equations, combining the concepts of quantity and space, and also the study of , which combine structure and space. are used to study space, structure, and change. in all its many ramifications may have been the greatest growth area in 20th-century mathematics; it includes , , and . In particular, instances of modern-day topology are , , , and . Topology also includes the now solved , and the still unsolved areas of the . Other results in geometry and topology, including the and , have been proven only with the help of computers.

Illustration to Euclid's proof of the Pythagorean theorem.svgSinusvg 400px.pngHyperbolic triangle.svgTorus.svgMandel zoom 07 satellite.jpgMeasure illustration (Vector).svg

Change

Main article:

Understanding and describing change is a common theme in the , and was developed as a tool to investigate it. arise here as a central concept describing a changing quantity. The rigorous study of and functions of a real variable is known as , with the equivalent field for the . focuses attention on (typically infinite-dimensional) of functions. One of many applications of functional analysis is . Many problems lead naturally to relationships between a quantity and its rate of change, and these are studied as . Many phenomena in nature can be described by ; makes precise the ways in which many of these systems exhibit unpredictable yet still behavior.

Integral as region under curve.svgVector field.svgNavier Stokes Laminar.svgLimitcycle.svgLorenz attractor.svgConformal grid after Mbius transformation.svg

Applied mathematics

Main article:

concerns itself with mathematical methods that are typically used in science, , , and . Thus, “applied mathematics” is a with specialized . The term applied mathematics also describes the professional specialty in which mathematicians work on practical problems; as a profession focused on practical problems, applied mathematics focuses on the “formulation, study, and use of mathematical models” in science, engineering, and other areas of mathematical practice.

In the past, practical applications have motivated the development of mathematical theories, which then became the subject of study in pure mathematics, where mathematics is developed primarily for its own sake. Thus, the activity of applied mathematics is vitally connected with research in .

Statistics and other decision sciences

Main article:

Applied mathematics has significant overlap with the discipline of statistics, whose theory is formulated mathematically, especially with . Statisticians (working as part of a research project) “create data that makes sense” with and with randomized ; the design of a statistical sample or experiment specifies the analysis of the data (before the data becomes available). When reconsidering data from experiments and samples or when analyzing data from , statisticians “make sense of the data” using the art of and the theory of with and ; the estimated models and consequential should be on .

studies such as minimizing the () of a statistical action, such as using a in, for example, , , and . In these traditional areas of , a statistical-decision problem is formulated by minimizing an , like expected loss or , under specific constraints: For example, designing a survey often involves minimizing the cost of estimating a population mean with a given level of confidence. Because of its use of , the mathematical theory of statistics shares concerns with other , such as , , and .

Computational mathematics

proposes and studies methods for solving that are typically too large for human numerical capacity. studies methods for problems in using and ; numerical analysis includes the study of and broadly with special concern for . Numerical analysis and, more broadly, scientific computing also study non-analytic topics of mathematical science, especially and . Other areas of computational mathematics include and .

Arbitrary-gametree-solved.svgBernoullisLawDerivationDiagram.svgComposite trapezoidal rule illustration small.svgMaximum boxed.pngTwo red dice 01.svgOldfaithful3.pngCaesar3.svgMarket Data Index NYA on 20050726 202628 UTC.pngGravitation space source.svgCH4-structure.svgSignal transduction pathways.svgGDP PPP Per Capita IMF 2008.svgSimple feedback control loop2.svg

Mathematical awards

Arguably the most prestigious award in mathematics is the , established in 1936 and awarded every four years (except around World War II) to as many as four individuals. The Fields Medal is often considered a mathematical equivalent to the Nobel Prize.

The , instituted in 1978, recognizes lifetime achievement, and another major international award, the , was instituted in 2003. The was introduced in 2010 to recognize lifetime achievement. These accolades are awarded in recognition of a particular body of work, which may be innovational, or provide a solution to an outstanding problem in an established field.

A famous list of 23 , called “”, was compiled in 1900 by German mathematician . This list achieved great celebrity among mathematicians, and at least nine of the problems have now been solved. A new list of seven important problems, titled the “”, was published in 2000. Only one of them, the , duplicates one of Hilbert’s problems. A solution to any of these problems carries a 1 million dollar reward. Currently, only one of these problems, the , has been solved.

See also

  • icon

Notes

  1. No likeness or description of Euclid’s physical appearance made during his lifetime survived antiquity. Therefore, Euclid’s depiction in works of art depends on the artist’s imagination (see ).
  2. See for simple examples of what can go wrong in a formal proof.
  3. For considering as reliable a large computation occurring in a proof, one generally requires two computations using independent software
  4. The book containing the complete proof has more than 1,000 pages.
  5. Like other mathematical sciences such as and , statistics is an autonomous discipline rather than a branch of applied mathematics. Like research physicists and computer scientists, research statisticians are mathematical scientists. Many statisticians have a degree in mathematics, and some statisticians are also mathematicians.

References

  1. ^ . Oxford English Dictionary. Oxford University Press. 2012. from the original on November 16, 2019. Retrieved June 16, 2012. The science of space, number, quantity, and arrangement, whose methods involve logical reasoning and usually the use of symbolic notation, and which includes geometry, arithmetic, algebra, and analysis.
  2. Kneebone, G.T. (1963). Mathematical Logic and the Foundations of Mathematics: An Introductory Survey. Dover. p. . . Mathematics … is simply the study of abstract structures, or formal patterns of connectedness.
  3. LaTorre, Donald R.; Kenelly, John W.; Biggers, Sherry S.; Carpenter, Laurel R.; Reed, Iris B.; Harris, Cynthia R. (2011). Calculus Concepts: An Informal Approach to the Mathematics of Change. Cengage Learning. p. . . Calculus is the study of changehow things change, and how quickly they change.
  4. Ramana (2007). Applied Mathematics. Tata McGrawHill Education. p. . . The mathematical study of change, motion, growth or decay is calculus.
  5. (2011). “What Is Mathematics?”. An Invitation to Mathematics: From Competitions to Research. Springer. p. . .
  6. ^ Mura, Roberta (December 1993). “Images of Mathematics Held by University Teachers of Mathematical Sciences”. Educational Studies in Mathematics. 25 (4): 37585. :. . .
  7. ^ & Helmut Neunzert (2012). . Springer. p. . . [I]t is first necessary to ask what is meant by mathematics in general. Illustrious scholars have debated this matter until they were blue in the face, and yet no consensus has been reached about whether mathematics is a natural science, a branch of the humanities, or an art form.
  8. (April 29, 1988). The Science of Patterns , 240: 61116. And summarized at October 28, 2010, at the , www.ascd.org.
  9. , Mathematics: The Science of Patterns: The Search for Order in Life, Mind and the Universe (Scientific American Paperback Library) 1996,
  10. Wise, David. . jwilson.coe.uga.edu. from the original on June 1, 2019. Retrieved October 26, 2019.
  11. , p. 306.
  12. , p. 12.
  13. ^ Wigner, Eugene (1960). . . 13 (1): 114. :. :. from the original on February 28, 2011.
  14. Dehaene, Stanislas; Dehaene-Lambertz, Ghislaine; Cohen, Laurent (August 1998). “Abstract representations of numbers in the animal and human brain”. Trends in Neurosciences. 21 (8): 35561. :. . .
  15. See, for example, Raymond L. Wilder, Evolution of Mathematical Concepts; an Elementary Study, passim
  16. Zaslavsky, Claudia. (1999). . Chicago Review Press. . . from the original on March 31, 2021. Retrieved May 29, 2020.
  17. , Chapter 1.
  18. . www.storyofmathematics.com. from the original on September 16, 2018. Retrieved October 27, 2019.
  19. ^ . www.storyofmathematics.com. from the original on September 7, 2019. Retrieved October 27, 2019.
  20. , “Mesopotamia” pp. 2427.
  21. Heath, Thomas Little (1981) [1921]. . New York: Dover Publications. p. . .
  22. , “Euclid of Alexandria” p. 119.
  23. , “Archimedes of Syracuse” p. 120.
  24. , “Archimedes of Syracuse” p. 130.
  25. , “Apollonius of Perga” p. 145.
  26. , “Greek Trigonometry and Mensuration” p. 162.
  27. , “Revival and Decline of Greek Mathematics” p. 180.
  28. ^ . www.storyofmathematics.com. from the original on April 13, 2019. Retrieved October 27, 2019.
  29. . www.storyofmathematics.com. from the original on October 17, 2019. Retrieved October 27, 2019.
  30. Saliba, George. (1994). . New York University Press. . . from the original on March 31, 2021. Retrieved May 29, 2020.
  31. . www.storyofmathematics.com. from the original on September 16, 2018. Retrieved October 27, 2019.
  32. . www.storyofmathematics.com. from the original on May 2, 2019. Retrieved October 27, 2019.
  33. . www.storyofmathematics.com. from the original on July 25, 2019. Retrieved October 27, 2019.
  34. . The Story of Mathematics. from the original on September 16, 2018. Retrieved October 27,2019.
  35. , pp. 10109.
  36. . . from the original on March 7, 2013.
  37. Both meanings can be found in Plato, the narrower in February 24, 2021, at the , but Plato did not use a math- word; Aristotle did, commenting on it. . ; ; at the . OED Online, “Mathematics”.
  38. . www.storyofmathematics.com. from the original on September 17, 2018. Retrieved October 27, 2019.
  39. (1995) [1991]. . Lion Hunting and Other Mathematical Pursuits: A Collection of Mathematics, Verse, and Stories by the Late Ralph P. Boas, Jr. Cambridge University Press. p. 257. . from the original on May 20, 2020. Retrieved January 17, 2018.
  40. , , sub“mathematics”, “mathematic”, “mathematics”
  41. and April 4, 2020, at the . Oxford English Dictionary, on-line version (2012).
  42. Franklin, James (July 8, 2009). . pp. 104106. . from the original on September 6, 2015. Retrieved July 1, 2020.
  43. (1893). A History of Mathematics. American Mathematical Society (1991 reprint). pp. . .
  44. ^ Snapper, Ernst (September 1979). “The Three Crises in Mathematics: Logicism, Intuitionism, and Formalism”. Mathematics Magazine. 52 (4): 20716. :. .
  45. (1882). . Van Nostrand. p. .
  46. Russell, Bertrand (1903). . p. . Retrieved June 20, 2015.
  47. Iemhoff, Rosalie (March 4, 2020). Zalta, Edward N. (ed.). . Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. from the original on March 31, 2021. Retrieved March 4, 2021 via Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
  48. (1951). Outlines of a Formalist Philosophy of Mathematics. Elsevier. p. . .
  49. , p. 79.
  50. du Sautoy, Marcus (June 25, 2010). . A Brief History of Mathematics. Event occurs at min. 12:50. BBC Radio 4. from the original on December 16, 2016. Retrieved October 26, 2017.
  51. , p. 56.
  52. Popper, Karl (2002) []. The Logic of Scientific Discovery. Abingdon-on-Thames: Routledge. p. [18]. .
  53. Bishop, Alan (1991). . Mathematical Enculturation: A Cultural Perspective on Mathematics Education. Norwell, Massachusetts: Kluwer Academic Publishers. pp. 2059. . from the original on December 25, 2020. Retrieved April 5, 2020.
  54. Shasha, Dennis Elliot; Lazere, Cathy A. (1998). Out of Their Minds: The Lives and Discoveries of 15 Great Computer Scientists. Springer. p. 228.
  55. Nickles, Thomas (2013). “The Problem of Demarcation”. Philosophy of Pseudoscience: Reconsidering the Demarcation Problem. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press. p. 104.
  56. , Massimo (2014). . . from the original on May 13, 2020. Retrieved April 6, 2020.
  57. See, for example ‘s statement “Mathematics, rightly viewed, possesses not only truth, but supreme beauty …” in his History of Western Philosophy
  58. . undsci.berkeley.edu. from the original on October 27, 2019. Retrieved October 27,2019.
  59. Borel, Armand (March 2017). . EMS Newsletter. 3 (103): 3745. :. .
  60. Meinhard E. Mayer (2001). “The Feynman Integral and Feynman’s Operational Calculus”. Physics Today. 54 (8): 48. :. :.
  61. Steiner, Mark (1998). The Applicability of Mathematics as a Philosophical Problem. Cambridge, Mass: Harvard University Press. p. 176. .
  62. ^ Leng, Mary (2010). Mathematics and Reality. Oxford University Press. p. 239. .
  63. (PDF). (PDF)from the original on May 14, 2011. Retrieved November 9, 2010.
  64. Hardy, G. H. (1940). A Mathematician’s Apology. Cambridge University Press. .
  65. ; Simons, Rogers A. (2008). Proof and Other Dilemmas: Mathematics and Philosophy. MAA.
  66. . from the original on February 20, 2016. Retrieved September 14, 2014.
  67. , p. 140, on ; p. 261, on .
  68. , p. 16: “Focused problem solving in math and science is often more effortful than focused-mode thinking involving language and people. This may be because humans haven’t evolved over the millennia to manipulate mathematical ideas, which are frequently more abstractly encrypted than those of conventional language.”
  69. , p. 16: “What do I mean by abstractness? You can point to a real live cow chewing its cud in a pasture and equate it with the letters cowon the page. But you can’t point to a real live plus sign that the symbol ‘+’ is modeled after the idea underlying the plus sign is more abstract.”
  70. , p. 16: “By encryptedness, I mean that one symbol can stand for a number of different operations or ideas, just as the multiplication sign symbolizes repeated addition.”
  71. Ivars Peterson, The Mathematical Tourist, Freeman, 1988, . p. 4 “A few complain that the computer program can’t be verified properly”, (in reference to the HakenApple proof of the Four Color Theorem).
  72. “The method of ‘postulating’ what we want has many advantages; they are the same as the advantages of theft over honest toil.” (1919), Introduction to Mathematical Philosophy, New York and London, June 20, 2015, at the
  73. Patrick Suppes, Axiomatic Set Theory, Dover, 1972, . p. 1, “Among the many branches of modern mathematics set theory occupies a unique place: with a few rare exceptions the entities which are studied and analyzed in mathematics may be regarded as certain particular sets or classes of objects.”
  74. Luke Howard Hodgkin & Luke Hodgkin, A History of Mathematics, Oxford University Press, 2005.
  75. Halpern, Joseph; Harper, Robert; Immerman, Neil; Kolaitis, Phokion; Vardi, Moshe; Vianu, Victor (2001). (PDF). Retrieved January 15, 2021.
  76. , P=NP, claymath.org
  77. (1997) Statistics and Truth: Putting Chance to Work, World Scientific.
  78. (1981). “Foreword”. In Arthanari, T.S.; (eds.). Mathematical programming in statistics. Wiley Series in Probability and Mathematical Statistics. New York: Wiley. pp. viiviii. . .
  79. , pp. 1011, 1418): (1994). . In (ed.). Probability, statistics and optimisation: A Tribute to Peter Whittle (previously “A realised path: The Cambridge Statistical Laboratory up to 1993 (revised 2002)” ed.). Chichester: John Wiley. pp. 128. . from the original on December 19, 2013.
  80. , p. 1: “The Fields Medal is now indisputably the best known and most influential award in mathematics.”
  81. , pp. 77882.

Bibliography

  • (1991). (2nd ed.). New York: Wiley. .
  • Eves, Howard (1990). An Introduction to the History of Mathematics (6th ed.). Saunders. .
  • (1990). (Paperback ed.). New York: Oxford University Press. .
  • Monastyrsky, Michael (2001). (PDF). CMS NOTES de la SMC. Canadian Mathematical Society. 33 (23). (PDF) from the original on August 13, 2006. Retrieved July 28, 2006.
  • (2014). . New York: Penguin Random House. . A Mind for Numbers.
  • (1881). (ed.). . American Journal of Mathematics (Corrected, expanded, and annotated revision with an 1875 paper by B. Peirce and annotations by his son, C.S. Peirce, of the 1872 lithograph ed.). 4 (14): 97229. :. :. . Corrected, expanded, and annotated revision with an 1875 paper by B. Peirce and annotations by his son, C. S. Peirce, of the 1872 lithograph ed. Google and as an extract, D. Van Nostrand, 1882, Google . from the original on March 31, 2021. Retrieved November 17, 2020..
  • Peterson, Ivars (2001). Mathematical Tourist, New and Updated Snapshots of Modern Mathematics. Owl Books. .
  • (1995). “On knowledge”. . New York: Routledge. :. .
  • Riehm, Carl (August 2002). (PDF). Notices of the AMS. 49 (7): 77872. (PDF) from the original on October 26, 2006. Retrieved October 2, 2006.
  • Sevryuk, Mikhail B. (January 2006). (PDF). . 43 (1): 10109. :. (PDF) from the original on July 23, 2006. Retrieved June 24, 2006.
  • (1965) [first published 1856]. Gauss zum Gedchtniss. Sndig Reprint Verlag H. R. Wohlwend. .

Further reading

Mathematicsat Wikipedia’s

  • from Wiktionary
  • from Wikimedia Commons
  • from Wikinews
  • from Wikiquote
  • from Wikisource
  • from Wikibooks
  • from Wikiversity

WikiversityAt , you can learn
more and teach others about Mathematics at the . about
Mathematics

  • Benson, Donald C. (2000). The Moment of Proof: Mathematical Epiphanies. Oxford University Press. .
  • Davis, Philip J.; Hersh, Reuben (1999). (Reprint ed.). Mariner Books. .
  • ; (1996). What Is Mathematics?: An Elementary Approach to Ideas and Methods(2nd ed.). New York: Oxford University Press. .
  • (1923). . E.P. Dutton & Co., New York. from the original on July 25, 2014. Retrieved September 23, 2012.
  • (1997). (1st ed.). W. W. Norton & Company. .
  • Hazewinkel, Michiel, ed. (2000). . Kluwer Academic Publishers.  A translated and expanded version of a Soviet mathematics encyclopedia, in ten volumes. Also in paperback and on CD-ROM, and July 3, 2011, at the .
  • Jourdain, Philip E. B. (2003). “The Nature of Mathematics”. In James R. Newman (ed.). The World of Mathematics. Dover Publications. .
  • Maier, Annaliese (1982). Steven Sargent (ed.). At the Threshold of Exact Science: Selected Writings of Annaliese Maier on Late Medieval Natural Philosophy. Philadelphia: University of Pennsylvania Press.
  • Pappas, Theoni (June 1989). The Joy Of Mathematics (Revised ed.). Wide World Publishing. .

hide

Mathematics ()

  • Category
  • Portal
  • Commons page
  • WikiProject

Edit this at Wikidata

  • :
  • :
  • :
  • :
  • :
  • :

Navigation menu

  • Not logged in

Search

Contribute

Tools

Print/export

In other projects

Languages

223 more

  • This page was last edited on 28 May 2021, at 11:16 (UTC).
  • Text is available under the ; additional terms may apply. By using this site, you agree to the and . Wikipedia is a registered trademark of